أهم المراجع
-
Claude Lévy-Strauss:
-
Les Structures élémentaires de la parenté Paris 1949.
-
Tristes Tropiques. Paris 1955.
-
Anthropologie structurale. Paris.
-
La Pensée sauvage 1962–1958.
-
Mythologiques (3 Vols.) Paris 1964–1968.
-
-
Jean-Paul Sartre: Critique de la raison dialectique. Paris (Gallimard) 1963.
-
J. Lacan: Ecrits. (Editions du seuil) 1966.
-
M. Foucault. Les Mots et le Choses. Gallimard 1966.
-
L. Althusser:
-
Lire Le Capital (2 vols.), 1965 (Maspéro).
-
Pour Marx 1965, (Maspéro).
-
Lénine et la philosophie 1970, (Maspéro).
-
Elements d’auto-critique 1974, (Hachette).
-
-
F. de Saussure: Cours de linguistique Générale (Payot) 1925.
-
Les Temps Modernes (numero spécial) Novemre 1966.
-
Structuralisme et marxisme (plusierus auteurs). Union Générale d’Edition, 1970.
-
J. Piaget: Structuralisme (English Trans.) Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1971.
-
F. Châtelet: Histoire de la philosophie. Tome 8. (Hachette) 1973.
-
E. Leach: Lévi-Strauss. London (Fontana Books) 1970.
-
Jean-Marie Auzias: Clafs pour le structuralisme. Paris (Seghers) 1967.
-
L. Sebag: Structuralisme et marxisme. (Payot), 1969.
-
J. Milhau: Chroniques philosophiques. (Editions Sociales), 1972.
The Philosophical Foundations of Structuralism
By: Dr. Fouad H.
Zakaria
(Summary)
(Summary)
The paper starts by stating that
structuralism, as a method, was known from ancient times,
while, as a total system of thought, it is a recent
phenomenon.
Its philosophical roots may be traced
to various sources, of which one of the most important is
Kant’s philosophy. The latter, too, was seeking an a-priori
schema within which the variety of experience may be
organized, consists of mental forms. Structuralism
constitutes one episode in the long series of attempts to
elevate the study of man to the level of rigorous science,
hence the important role played by the linguistic model in
it.
Philosophically speaking, the main
feature of structuralism is its opposition to empiricism on
the one hand and historicism on the other. According to it,
man’s mind and its cultural products grow organically, with
a hard core of forms which remain unchanged, although they
are incessantly elaborated and made more complex in the
process of growth. It is the discovery of these stable
elements which, for structuralism, justifies its claim to
be a rigorous scientific study of man and
society.
The paper gives an exposition of the
philosophical foundations of structuralism as examplified in
a few of its main representatives:
(1) Lévy-Strauss:
The philosophical formation of Strauss is
evident in the stress he lays on the role of the human mind
in moulding all of its cultural products. Man’s mind tends
to subsume various groups of experiences under one basic
structure, which forms the basis of all the apparent aspects
of social institutions. It was this philosophical character
of his research that provoked other anthropologists to
criticize him severely, on the ground that he dogmatically
kept his “structures” aloof from the stream of time. This
was also the origin of the famous controversy between
Strauss on the one hand, and Sartre and Existentialism on
the other.
(2) Michel
Foucault:
In his “Las Mots et Jes Choses”, Foucault
attempts to discover, in a non-historical manner, the
distinctive structure of each period in modern European
intellectual history since the Renaissance. He arbitrarily
fixes that structure to the point of neglecting many basic
elements without which each period would be
incomprehensible.
(3) The Structurlist
Marxists:
Lucien Sebag made an attempt to combine
Structuralism and Marxism on the ground that Marx was
seekig “total” forms or schemata which go beyond those
economic factors exclusively stressed by traditional
Marxism. The result was that Sebag denied the absolute
causality of the economic factor which, for him, formed only
a part of a much wider schema.
Louis Althusser’s attempt was more important.
He tried to restore the scientifically rigorous character of
Marxism, to stress its independance of Hegel and of the
whole previous philosophical tradition, and to found it on a
socio-economic structure of which man himself is only a
part.
He replaced traditional causality between the
infrastructure and the superstructure by a more complicated,
multiform causality. This attempt was criticized because of
its unilateral, arbitrary interpretation of Marxism as an
exact science, and its tendency to discard
Man.
The paper concludes by criticizing stucturalism
as a whole for the same reason, i. e. ignoring Man, together
with history and evolution. It is true that Piaget and Sebag
tried to reconcile structuralism with some sort of
historicism, through a more accurate definition of Man as
envisaged by structuralism. However, this defence was not
utterly convincing. Structuralism did not sufficiently take
into account the factors of movement, change and activity.
It stressed Man in his “static” condition, when he is acted
upon, instead of being active.